I have long been a fan of Michael' P.'s book that he quotes from here, especially this chapter. I would simply add that the term "fictitious capital" was not invented by Marx, although he gave it his own meaning (whatever that was, :-)). One can find it in Adam Smith and even earlier. The earlier uses clearly applied to speculative bubble prices for assets above some kind of what would now be called "fundamental". Smith used the term in his discussion of the South Sea Bubble of 1720 in Britain.
Sometimes in Marx it seems to have this meaning as well (although what the "fundamental" is is part of the problem in the definition), especially when he uses it in conjunction with his macro crisis theory. Many of the macro downturns of the nineteenth century were triggered by the collapses of speculative bubbles of one sort or another. Barkley Rosser On Thu, 20 Aug 1998 22:36:16 -0700 michael perelman <michael at ecst.csuchico.edu> wrote:
> Here is the beginning of my chapter on Fictitious Capital from my book on
> Marx's crisis theory.
> Fictitious Capital and the Crisis Theory
> Introduction
> Marx's theory of fictitious capital ties together the real and the monetary
> threads of his crisis theory. Despite the admitted gaps in Marx's incomplete
> analysis of fictitious capital, it represents an enormously valuable
> contribution. This enormously suggestive analysis serves as a corrective for
> some of the rather widely circulated, one-sided treatments of Marx's crisis
> theory. Moreover, it represents a remarkable anticipation of much of the
> recent mainstream macro-economic work on the role of asset values.
> Engels must have believed that Marx attributed substantial importance to the
> theory of fictitious capital. He laboriously collected a mass of Marx's
> obviously unfinished writings on fictitious capital into a separate chapter of
> the third volume of Capital. This chapter leaves little doubt that Marx had
> intended this subject to be an important component of the crisis theory that he
> was attempting to fashion. In contrast to Marx's strong interest in the
> concept of fictitious capital, his readers have largely ignored the subject,
> perhaps because Marx had not progressed very far with this analysis.
> Marx never gave a precise definition to the concept of fictitious capital, any
> more than he explicitly defined abstract labor, value or any of his other
> categories. For Marx, such concepts were to be understood in terms of their
> dialectical interrelationship with the whole body of analysis, which he
> offered. In his words, they are "a rich totality of many determinations and
> relations" (Marx 1974, p. 100).
> This practice allowed Marx's readers to suggest a number of contradictory
> explanations of his concepts. As Pareto complained in a previous citation,
> "Marx's words are like bats: one can see in them both birds and mice" (Pareto
> 1902: ii, p. 332; paraphrased by Ollman 1971, p. 3).
> No doubt, should the notion of fictitious capital come under more general
> scrutiny, it too would be given numerous interpretations. Let me merely say,
> at this point, that fictitious capital is basically the capitalization of
> future earnings (see Hilferding 1910, pp. 141 and 150), but this definition is
> far from exhaustive.
> Fictitious capital is important because it deflects value relationships from
> what they might have been if they had been formed in an abstract system
> resembling perfect competition. In a more concrete situation, these value
> relations are disturbed by the action of credit, speculation, and restrictive
> business practices.
> Despite the gaps in Marx's incomplete analysis of fictitious capital, it
> represents an enormously valuable contribution to his crisis theory. In the
> first place, it is suggestive in itself. Secondly, it serves as a corrective
> for some of the rather widely circulated, one-sided treatments of Marx's crisis
> theory. Finally, it represents a remarkable anticipation of much of the recent
> mainstream macro-economic work on the role of asset values.
> Because Marx left so much of this work unfinished, it remains for us to
> reconstruct much of this analysis. That task will necessarily be somewhat
> circuitous, but the resulting contribution to the understanding of crisis
> theory will more than justify the effort.
> My reconstruction of Marx's theory of fictitious capital follows the method
> that Marx used in Capital. Recall that he subtitled the first volume of
> Capital, "A Critique of Political Economy." Earlier, he had specifically
> referred to his work in political economy as a "critique of the economic
> categories" (Marx to Lassalle, 22 February 1858; in Marx and Engels 1975, p.
> 96). This reconstruction builds upon Marx's more or less complete analysis of
> the more familiar categories of classical political economy. Thus it requires
> a brief overview of Marx's method.
> Consider how Marx generally developed his analysis of the categories of
> political economy. His presentation of the contradictory nature of these
> categories was predicated on the previous work of classical political economy.
> Originally, these notions began as "chaotic conception[s]" (Marx 1977, p.
> 100). For the most part, classical political economy achieved a degree of
> coherence by submerging the contradictory tensions inherent in such
> categories. It managed to "have investigated the real internal framework of
> bourgeois relations of production, . . . to reduce the various fixed and
> mutually alien forms of wealth to their inner unity" (Marx 1963-1971; Pt. 3, p.
> 500; and 1977, pp. 174-75n).
> Marx, by contrast, explicitly took these contradictory forces into account.
> By incorporating such contradictions into his system, he discovered a richer
> level of analysis, with a more encompassing universe of coherence.
> Classical political economy produced a static, or a smoothly developing world
> view. Marx's created a theoretical analysis, which allowed for, and even
> emphasized, convulsive changes that were part of an intricate, but
> comprehensible system that included the general economic laws of motion. These
> forces that Marx studied propelled society from one system of social
> organization to another.
> These economic laws of motion characterized both society and the categories of
> political economy. The direction of this motion was two-dimensional: logical
> and historical. Logically, each category developed out of more abstract
> categories. According to this approach, historically, the most abstract
> categories took effect before the more concrete ones. Thus, Marx noted, "it is
> quite appropriate to regard the values of commodities as not only theoretically
> but also historically prius to the prices of production" (Marx 1967; 3, p.
> 177).
> I believe that Marx was in the process of extending this same sort of analysis
> to the category of fictitious capital. Given the unfinished state of his study
> of this subject, one can only infer the final shape of his intended
> presentation of fictitious capital. Based on the pattern of his more finished
> work, I believe that, logically, fictitious capital would have been presented
> as an extension of the price system. Historically, he would have treated it as
> emerging once credit becomes accepted as a supplement to commodity money
> (gold).
> The reconstruction of this process is complicated by the history of the
> analysis of fictitious capital within the literature of classical political
> economy. Unlike categories, such as wages, rent, or profits, fictitious
> capital had been inadequately processed by classical political economy. In
> fact, that category had never even achieved the status of an abstract category
> by classical political economy.
> Instead of a well-defined body of analysis, Marx was left with a jumble of
> conflicting perspectives. Thus, for the study of fictitious capital, he could
> not rely on the prior work of classical political economy. He had to make
> sense out of an amorphous mass of observations concerning fictitious capital.
> In addition, Marx himself had only belatedly recognized the importance of this
> category.
> A final difficulty in analyzing Marx's study of fictitious capital concerns
> the sequence of study of such material. Marx himself had noted, "the method of
> presentation must differ in form from that of inquiry" (Marx 1977, p. 102).
> Much of Marx's work on fictitious capital had not progressed beyond the stage
> of inquiry. It remains raw and tentative.
> So far, after asserting the value of studying Marx's analysis of fictitious
> capital, I have given what may seem to be a rather bleak appraisal of the
> prospects of such a study. Here is a category, not even recognized as such by
> classical political economy -- a category, which Marx had only begun to
> study. Could a review of such work ever be more than a Talmudic search for a
> few obscure phrases?
> Indeed, with the work of most writers, not much more could be expected.
> Fortunately, Marx is an exception. Because of the nature of his Hegelian
> method of presentation, one can extrapolate from his earlier work to get a
> partial understanding of what might be expected to have evolved, had he been
> able to give more study to the category of fictitious capital.
> To be sure, his analysis was somewhat sketchy, but it is highly suggestive.
> Even more fortunately, Marx frequently salted his notes on credit and
> fictitious capital with a number of very explicit passages, containing
> extraordinary insights concerning the nature of fictitious capital. In short,
> despite the obvious limitations of such material, it remains unsurpassed.
> Before presenting what Marx wrote about the subject of fictitious capital, I
> offer a brief survey of the previous use of the term, "fictitious capital." It
> appears formless and contradictory, but no more so than what was written about,
> say profit, before that category was subjugated to a more thorough analysis by
> classical political economy. After reviewing this material, I hope that you
> can appreciate the challenge Marx faced in developing his analysis of
> fictitious capital.
>
> --
> Michael Perelman
> Economics Department
> California State University
> Chico, CA 95929
>
> Tel. 530-898-5321
> E-Mail michael at ecst.csuchico.edu
>
>
-- Rosser Jr, John Barkley rosserjb at jmu.edu