Zizek on Havel

Yoshie Furuhashi furuhashi.1 at osu.edu
Tue Oct 26 02:13:58 PDT 1999


***** Havel's essay on 'The Power of the Powerless', written in 1978, was perceptive in explaining how Late Socialism operated at the domestic, day-to-day level. What was important was not that the people deep down believed in the ruling ideology, but that they followed the external rituals and practices by means of which this ideology acquired material existence. Havel's example is the greengrocer, a modest man profoundly indifferent to official ideology. He just mechanically follows the rules: on state holidays, he decorates the window of his shop with official slogans such as 'Long Live Socialism!' When there are mass gatherings he takes part affectlessly. Although he privately complains about the corruption and incompetence of 'those in power', he takes comfort in pieces of folk wisdom ('power corrupts' etc), which enable him to legitimise his stance in his own eyes and to retain a false appearance of dignity. When someone tries to engage him in dissident activity, he protests: 'Who are you to get me mixed up in things which are bound to be used against my children? Is it really up to me to set the world to rights?'

Havel saw that if there was a 'psychological' mechanism at work in Communist ideology, it was not to do with belief, but rather with shared guilt: in the 'normalisation' that followed the Soviet intervention of 1968, the Czech regime made sure that, in one way or another, the majority of people were somehow morally discredited, compelled to violate their own moral standards. When an individual was blackmailed into signing a petition against a dissident (Havel, for example), he knew that he was lying and taking part in a campaign against an honest man, and it was precisely this ethical betrayal that rendered him the ideal Communist subject. The regime relied on and actively condoned the moral bankruptcy of its subjects. Havel's concept of 'living in truth' involved no metaphysics: it simply designated the act of suspending one's participation, of breaking out of the vicious cycle of 'objective guilt'. He blocked off all the false escape-routes, including seeking refuge in the 'small pleasures of everyday life'. Such acts of indifference - making fun in private of official rituals, for instance - were, he said, the very means by which the official ideology was reproduced. <http://www.lrb.co.uk/v21/n21/zize2121.htm> *****

Here Zizek's recycling an interpretation of the work of ideology (which thrives in an ironic distance from ideology's truth claims) that he did best in _The Sublime Object of Ideology_. It seems to me that his recent Kantian turn -- with an emphasis upon the prohibition of the subjective assumption of Historical Necessity -- is at cross-purposes with his earlier neo-Althusserian mode. The early Zizek basically says that it really doesn't matter what you believe, as long as you are behaving as expected, the point is to quit doing what you are doing, whereas the late Zizek seeks to salvage the concept of ethics from the ruins of the subject. Doesn't Zizek's Kantian turn have something to do with his work for the post-socialist ruling party, with his professed goal of guarding liberal pluralism? One can turn Zizek's critique of Havel against Zizek himself -- now it does matter to Zizek what morality people subscribe to (ideally, for Zizek, a Lacanian-Kantian ethics of personal responsibility in the face of utter neo-liberal uncertainty), for he has to guard the status quo ('against nationalist excesses' would be his excuse, ironically because he criticizes the West for projecting "an idea of the Balkans as the phantasmatic space of nationalist madness") whereas earlier his reading of ideology paid closer attention to exactly what maintains the status quo, with a view to changing it (though he never explained how we might go about doing so, given his dismissal of traditional concepts of agency, be they bourgeois or Marxist).

Yoshie



More information about the lbo-talk mailing list