<HTML><FONT FACE=arial,helvetica><FONT SIZE=2>Chuck Grimes writes:
<BR><< But it is space, the external form of physical reality independent of any
<BR>mental construct that is the ground of these symmetries. They are not an
<BR>artifact of human perception and cognition. The empirical proof of this is
<BR>found in crystallography where spatial symmetries are expressed physically as
<BR>chemically formed atomic lattice structures. In other words there is
<BR>structure to physical reality, and our constructs of the world are formed
<BR>through our interaction with these structures, which exist apriori to our
<BR>mental formulation of them. >>
<BR>
<BR>Linguistics is an area where my curiosity far outstrips my knowledge, so I
<BR>more inclined to ask questions than stake out positions. I know a bit more
<BR>about Piaget, given his role in education theory. I think Chuck's account of
<BR>his work is generally on target, although I do not remember mathematics being
<BR>as central to the theory as Chuck's suggests. Spatial organization, yes;
<BR>mathematics, not so much.
<BR>
<BR>My question relates to the way in which Chuck (or is it the voice of Piaget?)
<BR>presents spatial organization, as external and prior to human perception and
<BR>organization. I am skeptical of this claim. To begin with, I think it is
<BR>clear that human beings have not simply understood the organization of space
<BR>differently at different times, but also organized space in some quite
<BR>different ways throughout their history. In this respect, it is instructive
<BR>to look at the form of maps in different historical periods -- cartographers
<BR>talk about maps embodying a cosmology.
<BR>
<BR>Now, clearly there is a materiality of space which precedes human
<BR>organization of it; it would be absurd to deny otherwise. But the concept of
<BR>'space' is somewhat like the concept of 'nature': the very notion of nature
<BR>(of a living, material world, with its own 'laws', separate and distinct from
<BR>human beings) is a product of a human discursive organization which
<BR>establishes 'nature' as something outside of us. Thus, the opposition of
<BR>'nature' and 'culture'/'history'. Many human cultures do not recognize or see
<BR>this separation and opposition, and have no concept of nature as such. One
<BR>can say, therefore, that for human beings, there is no 'nature' other than
<BR>that we appropriate through our discourse. Similarly, one could make the case
<BR>that for human beings, there is no 'space' outside of our discursive
<BR>organization of the world around us. To use Kantian language, it is
<BR>impossible to "know" nature or space [the thing in itself]; our knowledge is
<BR>always mediated by our discursive construction of the object we are studying.
<BR>Thus, insofar as Piaget sees "space" as a purely or solely 'pre-given,' he
<BR>fails to grasp the element of human subjectivity -- and the role of human
<BR>history -- in the constitution of that "space." Like Freud, therefore, he
<BR>mistakes stages of human development which are culturally and historically
<BR>specific, as universal. Does this make sense to those of us who know
<BR>linguistics a whole lot better than I?
<BR>
<BR>Leo Casey
<BR>United Federation of Teachers
<BR>260 Park Avenue South
<BR>New York, New York 10010-7272 (212-598-6869)
<BR>
<BR>Power concedes nothing without a demand.
<BR>It never has, and it never will.
<BR>If there is no struggle, there is no progress.
<BR>Those who profess to favor freedom, and yet deprecate agitation are men who
<BR>want crops without plowing the ground. They want rain without thunder and
<BR>lightning. They want the ocean without the awful roar of its waters.
<BR><P ALIGN=CENTER>-- Frederick Douglass --</P></FONT></HTML>